Skip to main content
ScienceSpiegeloog 426: Liberation

Ambiguity of the Wandering Mind

By May 15, 2023No Comments

Think back to the past; you’re in the sixth grade and your language teacher is very effectively putting you to sleep with her words. You know you can’t afford to fall asleep in class unless you want to risk the wrath of your teacher and a complaint-ridden mother, so you resort to the next best alternative. You sleep with your eyes open; you daydream. Your mind will wander, not fulfiling the longing ache for actual sleep, but fulfiling the wish to drift away, to leave your stuffy classroom and go someplace else. Perhaps this disillusioned disconnecting may aid your focus in a roundabout way or it may warrant the stamp of distraction upon your report card. But as with anything theoretical or physical, it is probably best when practised in moderation. Which begs the question; can daydreaming lead to more severe forms of dissociation and impede on the dreamer’s daily life? It is all rather contextual, but the pretext to seemingly harmless drifting runs far deeper than an attempt to quell boredom.

Think back to the past; you’re in the sixth grade and your language teacher is very effectively putting you to sleep with her words. You know you can’t afford to fall asleep in class unless you want to risk the wrath of your teacher and a complaint-ridden mother, so you resort to the next best alternative. You sleep with your eyes open; you daydream. Your mind will wander, not fulfiling the longing ache for actual sleep, but fulfiling the wish to drift away, to leave your stuffy classroom and go someplace else. Perhaps this disillusioned disconnecting may aid your focus in a roundabout way or it may warrant the stamp of distraction upon your report card. But as with anything theoretical or physical, it is probably best when practised in moderation. Which begs the question; can daydreaming lead to more severe forms of dissociation and impede on the dreamer’s daily life? It is all rather contextual, but the pretext to seemingly harmless drifting runs far deeper than an attempt to quell boredom.

Illustration by Arianna Cavalli

Illustration by Arianna Cavalli

“Dissociation can be broadly understood as alterations in consciousness where integrated processing of psychological and/or sensory information is disrupted” (Dorahy, M. J., & Lewis, C. A. (2001). Dissociation as a symptom in fact holds the bragging rights to an entire category of mental disorders that include Dissociative Identity Disorder, Depersonalisation-Derealisation Disorder and Dissociative Amnesia. Now let’s look at the definition of a term, or rather state of mind, that could very well be a cousin of dissociation– daydreaming. ‘Daydreaming mentally transports people to another place or time’, something dissociation also does – often as an attempt to cope with traumatic experiences. At their core, traumatic experiences are instances in people’s lives that they often wish to forget completely.

“Many daydreams are similar in content to the thoughts that people generate when they intentionally try to forget. Thus, thoughts like those generated during daydreaming can cause forgetting of previously encoded events.” (Delaney, P. F., et.al. (2010). As is evident through their definitions alone, these two terms seem to have a lot in common. But is there a definitive distinction that lets us know when daydreaming teeters on the edge of becoming dissociation? The answer may lie within the source that creates the need to daydream, it may be a coping method to grasp at freedom and liberate oneself from the hold a traumatic event has on them. It may also very well just be the freedom provided by mentally checking out.

Thomas Hoccleve, a clerk, court poet, and a key literary figure in the 15th century, was also a victim of severe episodes of mental illness, including insomnia. Hisashi Sugito discusses the insomniac’s creative process that is in part reliant on his daydreaming: “Hoccleve, afflicted with melancholic thought, describes his feelings as dull and heavy, and the dullness makes his mind asleep even when he is awake”, unable to connect while truly awake he dreams to conjure the wit for his work. “Hoccleve develops the dream vision tradition to a paradoxical extreme: while he remains in reality, he reaches a dreamworld with his daydreaming mind” (Sugito, H. (2014). This is the perfect account of a successful daydreamer to study, for he has both components of what we are attempting to scrutinise under the lens of reality. There are many of us who have to resort to rather creative methods to stay focused. For Hoccleve this was daydreaming, and indeed it worked for him as is evident in his historic success; but he also had a history of being inflicted with bouts of mental illnesses, so how do we know his daydreaming would still help him had he never had an episode of mental illness? There are many studies that would suggest daydreaming on its own without any other affliction greater than a lack of concentration would still elevate productivity, such as an interesting piece of research that summarises this old versus new opinion on the matter: “Daydreams have usually been associated with idleness and inattentiveness. Now, however, through an empirical research program, their general function and adaptive possibilities are being elucidated.” (Singer, 1974).

“Daydreaming is a part of your routine. Whether it helps you or makes you your own worst enemy.”

Now that we have observed daydreaming and its dissociative potential, we can discuss the possibility of the wider implication of its controversial nature. What are the cultural limits of its rationality? There is no evidence of daydreaming being a universal phenomenon, and perhaps the philosophical musings surrounding escapism and existentialism play a far more important role in modern psychology (Solomon,1992). These concepts were new and metaphorical for their time but in the context of daydreaming and dissociative disorders we have a grey area which we can utilise to understand the concept of using these methods to theorise trauma. While avoidance and denial are harmful in the long run, daydreaming begets the peace of one’s own mind, which we are mostly in control of. This would be a positive method of coping. Although this theoretical rationalisation gives way to a completely different argument of free will versus determinism, there is sufficient evidence of free will in psychology to suggest the mindscape does to some extent bend to our will (Baumeister, R. F. (2008), (ULLRICH, D. W. (2011). Certain people were found to be more susceptible to daydreaming and dissociation in the context of self-preservation and trauma suppression, and a wide portion of this demographic includes survivors of childhood trauma and sexual abuse. These survivors according to the ‘trauma betrayal theory’ learn how to compartmentalise their traumatic experiences from conscious awareness by dividing attention using methods such as dissociating (Giesbrecht & Merckelbach, 2009). Such data and studies support the concept of theorising trauma that was mentioned earlier.

Whether you’re a child with a chronic need to constantly escape the boring reality of your literature homework, or if you’ve reached adulthood and are tested by that same escapist temptation that interferes with your ability to meet deadlines in the unforgiving corporate world. Or maybe you are one of the few we can generalise the findings of controversial ‘daydreaming boosts productivity’ studies to. The bottom line is that daydreaming is a part of your routine. Whether it helps you or makes you your own worst enemy, whether you are wholly unaware of it even happening – it is completely situational. Nobody daydreams the same and no two daydreamers would have the exact same reason for doing so. Self awareness is not a metaphor or crutch to justify digging deeper into the mechanisms of daydreaming, it is a means to tether you to yourself as is evidenced by the concept of free will. We must retain it in order to use daydreaming and dissociation as a positive coping mechanism. While such a statement is rather conflicting in nature, it’s important to understand that the liberation we attempt by drifting into our own minds is constituted by the very belief of free will and freedom of mind. In the account of yourself as a wanderer you must assign it purpose: “Mind-wandering is unguided attention: accounting for the “purposeful” wanderer” (Irving, Z. C. (2016).

References

  • Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free Will in Scientific Psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3(1), 14–19. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40212223
  • Dorahy, M. J., & Lewis, C. A. (2001). The Relationship between Dissociation and Religiosity: An Empirical Evaluation of Schumaker’s Theory. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 40(2), 315–322. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1387953
  • Delaney, P. F., Sahakyan, L., Kelley, C. M., & Zimmerman, C. A. (2010). Remembering to Forget: The Amnesic Effect of Daydreaming. Psychological Science, 21(7), 1036–1042. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41062463
  • GIESBRECHT, T., & MERCKELBACH, H. (2009). Betrayal trauma theory of dissociative experiences: Stroop and directed forgetting findings. The American Journal of Psychology, 122(3), 337–348. http://www.jstor.org/stable/27784407
  • Glausiusz, J. (2011). Living in a Dream World. Scientific American Mind, 22(1), 24–31. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24943266
  • Heilmann, M. (2011). Obsessive-Compulsive Daydreaming. Art Journal, 70(2), 42–49. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41430724
  • Irving, Z. C. (2016). Mind-wandering is unguided attention: accounting for the “purposeful” wanderer. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 173(2), 547–571. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24703898
  • Kermode, F. (1957). Dissociation of Sensibility. The Kenyon Review, 19(2), 169–194. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4333745
  • Löfgren, O., & Ehn, B. (2007). Daydreaming Between Dusk and Dawn. Etnofoor, 20(2), 9–21. http://www.jstor.org/stable/25758137
  • Nicholas Rescher. (2014). Evidentiating Free Will. The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 28(1), 79–106. https://doi.org/10.5325/jspecphil.28.1.0079
  • Schönfelder, C. (2013). Theorizing Trauma: Romantic and Postmodern Perspectives on Mental Wounds. In Wounds and Words: Childhood and Family Trauma in Romantic and Postmodern Fiction (pp. 27–86). Transcript Verlag. http://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctv1wxrhq.5
  • Singer, J. L. (1974). Daydreaming and the Stream of Thought: Daydreams have usually been associated with idleness and inattentiveness. Now, however, through an empirical research program, their general function and adaptive possibilities are being elucidated. American Scientist, 62(4), 417–425. http://www.jstor.org/stable/27844990
  • Solomon, R. C. (1992 Existentialism, Emotions, and the Cultural Limits of Rationality. Philosophy East and West, 42(4), 597–621. https://doi.org/10.2307/1399671
  • Sugito, H. (2014). Reality as Dream: Hoccleve’s Daydreaming Mind. The Chaucer Review, 49(2), 244–263. https://doi.org/10.5325/chaucerrev.49.2.0244
  • Thompson, C. (2007). Kant’s Daydreaming. The American Poetry Review, 36(4), 40–40. http://www.jstor.org/stable/20683610
  • ULLRICH, D. W. (2011). Free Will versus Determinism in “This Side of Paradise”: Bodily Signifiers, Heredity, and Altruism in Fitzgerald’s First Novel. The F. Scott Fitzgerald Review, 9, 41–67. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41608005
  • Walsh, S. (2018). IN DEFENCE OF FORGETTING. In P. TORTELL, M. TURIN, & M. YOUNG (Eds.), Memory (pp. 173–180). Peter Wall Institute for Advanced Studies. https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctvbtzpfm.23

“Dissociation can be broadly understood as alterations in consciousness where integrated processing of psychological and/or sensory information is disrupted” (Dorahy, M. J., & Lewis, C. A. (2001). Dissociation as a symptom in fact holds the bragging rights to an entire category of mental disorders that include Dissociative Identity Disorder, Depersonalisation-Derealisation Disorder and Dissociative Amnesia. Now let’s look at the definition of a term, or rather state of mind, that could very well be a cousin of dissociation– daydreaming. ‘Daydreaming mentally transports people to another place or time’, something dissociation also does – often as an attempt to cope with traumatic experiences. At their core, traumatic experiences are instances in people’s lives that they often wish to forget completely.

“Many daydreams are similar in content to the thoughts that people generate when they intentionally try to forget. Thus, thoughts like those generated during daydreaming can cause forgetting of previously encoded events.” (Delaney, P. F., et.al. (2010). As is evident through their definitions alone, these two terms seem to have a lot in common. But is there a definitive distinction that lets us know when daydreaming teeters on the edge of becoming dissociation? The answer may lie within the source that creates the need to daydream, it may be a coping method to grasp at freedom and liberate oneself from the hold a traumatic event has on them. It may also very well just be the freedom provided by mentally checking out.

Thomas Hoccleve, a clerk, court poet, and a key literary figure in the 15th century, was also a victim of severe episodes of mental illness, including insomnia. Hisashi Sugito discusses the insomniac’s creative process that is in part reliant on his daydreaming: “Hoccleve, afflicted with melancholic thought, describes his feelings as dull and heavy, and the dullness makes his mind asleep even when he is awake”, unable to connect while truly awake he dreams to conjure the wit for his work. “Hoccleve develops the dream vision tradition to a paradoxical extreme: while he remains in reality, he reaches a dreamworld with his daydreaming mind” (Sugito, H. (2014). This is the perfect account of a successful daydreamer to study, for he has both components of what we are attempting to scrutinise under the lens of reality. There are many of us who have to resort to rather creative methods to stay focused. For Hoccleve this was daydreaming, and indeed it worked for him as is evident in his historic success; but he also had a history of being inflicted with bouts of mental illnesses, so how do we know his daydreaming would still help him had he never had an episode of mental illness? There are many studies that would suggest daydreaming on its own without any other affliction greater than a lack of concentration would still elevate productivity, such as an interesting piece of research that summarises this old versus new opinion on the matter: “Daydreams have usually been associated with idleness and inattentiveness. Now, however, through an empirical research program, their general function and adaptive possibilities are being elucidated.” (Singer, 1974).

“Daydreaming is a part of your routine. Whether it helps you or makes you your own worst enemy.”

Now that we have observed daydreaming and its dissociative potential, we can discuss the possibility of the wider implication of its controversial nature. What are the cultural limits of its rationality? There is no evidence of daydreaming being a universal phenomenon, and perhaps the philosophical musings surrounding escapism and existentialism play a far more important role in modern psychology (Solomon,1992). These concepts were new and metaphorical for their time but in the context of daydreaming and dissociative disorders we have a grey area which we can utilise to understand the concept of using these methods to theorise trauma. While avoidance and denial are harmful in the long run, daydreaming begets the peace of one’s own mind, which we are mostly in control of. This would be a positive method of coping. Although this theoretical rationalisation gives way to a completely different argument of free will versus determinism, there is sufficient evidence of free will in psychology to suggest the mindscape does to some extent bend to our will (Baumeister, R. F. (2008), (ULLRICH, D. W. (2011). Certain people were found to be more susceptible to daydreaming and dissociation in the context of self-preservation and trauma suppression, and a wide portion of this demographic includes survivors of childhood trauma and sexual abuse. These survivors according to the ‘trauma betrayal theory’ learn how to compartmentalise their traumatic experiences from conscious awareness by dividing attention using methods such as dissociating (Giesbrecht & Merckelbach, 2009). Such data and studies support the concept of theorising trauma that was mentioned earlier.

Whether you’re a child with a chronic need to constantly escape the boring reality of your literature homework, or if you’ve reached adulthood and are tested by that same escapist temptation that interferes with your ability to meet deadlines in the unforgiving corporate world. Or maybe you are one of the few we can generalise the findings of controversial ‘daydreaming boosts productivity’ studies to. The bottom line is that daydreaming is a part of your routine. Whether it helps you or makes you your own worst enemy, whether you are wholly unaware of it even happening – it is completely situational. Nobody daydreams the same and no two daydreamers would have the exact same reason for doing so. Self awareness is not a metaphor or crutch to justify digging deeper into the mechanisms of daydreaming, it is a means to tether you to yourself as is evidenced by the concept of free will. We must retain it in order to use daydreaming and dissociation as a positive coping mechanism. While such a statement is rather conflicting in nature, it’s important to understand that the liberation we attempt by drifting into our own minds is constituted by the very belief of free will and freedom of mind. In the account of yourself as a wanderer you must assign it purpose: “Mind-wandering is unguided attention: accounting for the “purposeful” wanderer” (Irving, Z. C. (2016).

References

  • Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free Will in Scientific Psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3(1), 14–19. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40212223
  • Dorahy, M. J., & Lewis, C. A. (2001). The Relationship between Dissociation and Religiosity: An Empirical Evaluation of Schumaker’s Theory. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 40(2), 315–322. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1387953
  • Delaney, P. F., Sahakyan, L., Kelley, C. M., & Zimmerman, C. A. (2010). Remembering to Forget: The Amnesic Effect of Daydreaming. Psychological Science, 21(7), 1036–1042. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41062463
  • GIESBRECHT, T., & MERCKELBACH, H. (2009). Betrayal trauma theory of dissociative experiences: Stroop and directed forgetting findings. The American Journal of Psychology, 122(3), 337–348. http://www.jstor.org/stable/27784407
  • Glausiusz, J. (2011). Living in a Dream World. Scientific American Mind, 22(1), 24–31. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24943266
  • Heilmann, M. (2011). Obsessive-Compulsive Daydreaming. Art Journal, 70(2), 42–49. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41430724
  • Irving, Z. C. (2016). Mind-wandering is unguided attention: accounting for the “purposeful” wanderer. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 173(2), 547–571. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24703898
  • Kermode, F. (1957). Dissociation of Sensibility. The Kenyon Review, 19(2), 169–194. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4333745
  • Löfgren, O., & Ehn, B. (2007). Daydreaming Between Dusk and Dawn. Etnofoor, 20(2), 9–21. http://www.jstor.org/stable/25758137
  • Nicholas Rescher. (2014). Evidentiating Free Will. The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 28(1), 79–106. https://doi.org/10.5325/jspecphil.28.1.0079
  • Schönfelder, C. (2013). Theorizing Trauma: Romantic and Postmodern Perspectives on Mental Wounds. In Wounds and Words: Childhood and Family Trauma in Romantic and Postmodern Fiction (pp. 27–86). Transcript Verlag. http://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctv1wxrhq.5
  • Singer, J. L. (1974). Daydreaming and the Stream of Thought: Daydreams have usually been associated with idleness and inattentiveness. Now, however, through an empirical research program, their general function and adaptive possibilities are being elucidated. American Scientist, 62(4), 417–425. http://www.jstor.org/stable/27844990
  • Solomon, R. C. (1992 Existentialism, Emotions, and the Cultural Limits of Rationality. Philosophy East and West, 42(4), 597–621. https://doi.org/10.2307/1399671
  • Sugito, H. (2014). Reality as Dream: Hoccleve’s Daydreaming Mind. The Chaucer Review, 49(2), 244–263. https://doi.org/10.5325/chaucerrev.49.2.0244
  • Thompson, C. (2007). Kant’s Daydreaming. The American Poetry Review, 36(4), 40–40. http://www.jstor.org/stable/20683610
  • ULLRICH, D. W. (2011). Free Will versus Determinism in “This Side of Paradise”: Bodily Signifiers, Heredity, and Altruism in Fitzgerald’s First Novel. The F. Scott Fitzgerald Review, 9, 41–67. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41608005
  • Walsh, S. (2018). IN DEFENCE OF FORGETTING. In P. TORTELL, M. TURIN, & M. YOUNG (Eds.), Memory (pp. 173–180). Peter Wall Institute for Advanced Studies. https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctvbtzpfm.23
Aniya Khokar

Author Aniya Khokar

More posts by Aniya Khokar